The Philosopher in Plato’s Statesman [electronic resource] /

others in his discipline tend not to bring their studies to bear on the substance of the dialogues. Conversely, philosophical interpreters have generally felt free to approach the extensive logical and ontological, cosmological, and political doctrines of the later dialogues without concern for questions of literary style s and form. Given, moreover, the equally sharp distinction between the diSCiplines of philosophy and cultural history, it has been too easy to treat this bulk of doctrine without a pointed sense of the specific historical audience to which it is addressed. As a result, the pervasive tendency has been the reverse of that which has dominated the reading of the early dialogues: here we tend to neglect drama and pedagogy and to focus exclusively on philosophical substance. Both in general and particularly in regard to the later dialogues, the difficulty is that our predispositions have the force of self-fulfilling prophecy. Are we sure that the later Plato's apparent loss of interest in the dramatic is not, on the contrary, a reflection of our limited sense of the integrity of drama and sub­ stance, form and content? What we lack eyes for, of course, we will not see. The basic purpose of this essay is to develop eyes, as it were, for that integrity. The best way to do this, I think, is to take a later dialogue and to try to read it as a whole of form, content, and communicative function.

Saved in:
Bibliographic Details
Main Authors: Miller, Mitchell H. author., SpringerLink (Online service)
Format: Texto biblioteca
Language:eng
Published: Dordrecht : Springer Netherlands, 1980
Subjects:Philosophy., Philosophy, Ancient., Classical Philosophy.,
Online Access:http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-8790-6
Tags: Add Tag
No Tags, Be the first to tag this record!
id KOHA-OAI-TEST:182436
record_format koha
institution COLPOS
collection Koha
country México
countrycode MX
component Bibliográfico
access En linea
En linea
databasecode cat-colpos
tag biblioteca
region America del Norte
libraryname Departamento de documentación y biblioteca de COLPOS
language eng
topic Philosophy.
Philosophy, Ancient.
Philosophy.
Classical Philosophy.
Philosophy.
Philosophy, Ancient.
Philosophy.
Classical Philosophy.
spellingShingle Philosophy.
Philosophy, Ancient.
Philosophy.
Classical Philosophy.
Philosophy.
Philosophy, Ancient.
Philosophy.
Classical Philosophy.
Miller, Mitchell H. author.
SpringerLink (Online service)
The Philosopher in Plato’s Statesman [electronic resource] /
description others in his discipline tend not to bring their studies to bear on the substance of the dialogues. Conversely, philosophical interpreters have generally felt free to approach the extensive logical and ontological, cosmological, and political doctrines of the later dialogues without concern for questions of literary style s and form. Given, moreover, the equally sharp distinction between the diSCiplines of philosophy and cultural history, it has been too easy to treat this bulk of doctrine without a pointed sense of the specific historical audience to which it is addressed. As a result, the pervasive tendency has been the reverse of that which has dominated the reading of the early dialogues: here we tend to neglect drama and pedagogy and to focus exclusively on philosophical substance. Both in general and particularly in regard to the later dialogues, the difficulty is that our predispositions have the force of self-fulfilling prophecy. Are we sure that the later Plato's apparent loss of interest in the dramatic is not, on the contrary, a reflection of our limited sense of the integrity of drama and sub­ stance, form and content? What we lack eyes for, of course, we will not see. The basic purpose of this essay is to develop eyes, as it were, for that integrity. The best way to do this, I think, is to take a later dialogue and to try to read it as a whole of form, content, and communicative function.
format Texto
topic_facet Philosophy.
Philosophy, Ancient.
Philosophy.
Classical Philosophy.
author Miller, Mitchell H. author.
SpringerLink (Online service)
author_facet Miller, Mitchell H. author.
SpringerLink (Online service)
author_sort Miller, Mitchell H. author.
title The Philosopher in Plato’s Statesman [electronic resource] /
title_short The Philosopher in Plato’s Statesman [electronic resource] /
title_full The Philosopher in Plato’s Statesman [electronic resource] /
title_fullStr The Philosopher in Plato’s Statesman [electronic resource] /
title_full_unstemmed The Philosopher in Plato’s Statesman [electronic resource] /
title_sort philosopher in plato’s statesman [electronic resource] /
publisher Dordrecht : Springer Netherlands,
publishDate 1980
url http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-8790-6
work_keys_str_mv AT millermitchellhauthor thephilosopherinplatosstatesmanelectronicresource
AT springerlinkonlineservice thephilosopherinplatosstatesmanelectronicresource
AT millermitchellhauthor philosopherinplatosstatesmanelectronicresource
AT springerlinkonlineservice philosopherinplatosstatesmanelectronicresource
_version_ 1756264960226230272
spelling KOHA-OAI-TEST:1824362018-07-30T23:03:11ZThe Philosopher in Plato’s Statesman [electronic resource] / Miller, Mitchell H. author. SpringerLink (Online service) textDordrecht : Springer Netherlands,1980.engothers in his discipline tend not to bring their studies to bear on the substance of the dialogues. Conversely, philosophical interpreters have generally felt free to approach the extensive logical and ontological, cosmological, and political doctrines of the later dialogues without concern for questions of literary style s and form. Given, moreover, the equally sharp distinction between the diSCiplines of philosophy and cultural history, it has been too easy to treat this bulk of doctrine without a pointed sense of the specific historical audience to which it is addressed. As a result, the pervasive tendency has been the reverse of that which has dominated the reading of the early dialogues: here we tend to neglect drama and pedagogy and to focus exclusively on philosophical substance. Both in general and particularly in regard to the later dialogues, the difficulty is that our predispositions have the force of self-fulfilling prophecy. Are we sure that the later Plato's apparent loss of interest in the dramatic is not, on the contrary, a reflection of our limited sense of the integrity of drama and sub­ stance, form and content? What we lack eyes for, of course, we will not see. The basic purpose of this essay is to develop eyes, as it were, for that integrity. The best way to do this, I think, is to take a later dialogue and to try to read it as a whole of form, content, and communicative function.I. The Dramatic Context -- 1. Dramatic situation: the trial of Socrates -- 2. Dramatis personae: antipathy, eagerness, silence -- 3. The stranger from Elea -- 4. The agreement to begin -- II. The Initial Diairesis (258b–267c) -- 1. Formal structure of the method; the apparent accord (258b–261e) -- 2. Young Socrates’ error; the value of bifurcatory diairesis (261e–264b) -- 3. The closing bifurcations; jokes and problems (264b–267c) -- III. The Digressions on Substance and Method (267c–287b) -- A. The first digression: the myth of the divine shepherd (267c–277a) -- B. The second digression: paradigm and the mean (277a–287b) -- IV. The Final Diairesis (287b–311c) -- a. The change in the form of diairesis (287b ff.) -- b. The first phase: the indirectly responsible arts, makers of instruments (287b–289c) -- c. The second phase, part one: the directly responsible arts, subaltern servants (289c–290e) -- d. The digression: philosophy and ordinary opinion; statesmanship and actual political order (291a–303d) -- e. Resumption of the diairesis (second phase, part two): the true aides (303d–305e) -- f. The third phase: the statesman as weaver; the virtues and the mean (305e–311c) -- Notes -- Index of Historical Persons -- Index of References to Platonic Passages.others in his discipline tend not to bring their studies to bear on the substance of the dialogues. Conversely, philosophical interpreters have generally felt free to approach the extensive logical and ontological, cosmological, and political doctrines of the later dialogues without concern for questions of literary style s and form. Given, moreover, the equally sharp distinction between the diSCiplines of philosophy and cultural history, it has been too easy to treat this bulk of doctrine without a pointed sense of the specific historical audience to which it is addressed. As a result, the pervasive tendency has been the reverse of that which has dominated the reading of the early dialogues: here we tend to neglect drama and pedagogy and to focus exclusively on philosophical substance. Both in general and particularly in regard to the later dialogues, the difficulty is that our predispositions have the force of self-fulfilling prophecy. Are we sure that the later Plato's apparent loss of interest in the dramatic is not, on the contrary, a reflection of our limited sense of the integrity of drama and sub­ stance, form and content? What we lack eyes for, of course, we will not see. The basic purpose of this essay is to develop eyes, as it were, for that integrity. The best way to do this, I think, is to take a later dialogue and to try to read it as a whole of form, content, and communicative function.Philosophy.Philosophy, Ancient.Philosophy.Classical Philosophy.Springer eBookshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-8790-6URN:ISBN:9789400987906